TACIT COERCION: A REPLY

Authors

  • Stephen P. Turner University of South Florida

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202461344

Keywords:

tacit knowledge, epistemic coercion, expertise, censorship, power

Abstract

In this reply to comments by Schliesser, Kochin, Kositna, Sassower, Miller, and Eyal and Sheremet, the underlying thesis of “Epistemic Coercion” is elaborated and explained. Epistemic coercion is often thought to be impossible: no one can coerce belief. This is the thesis of epistemic voluntarism. But the techniques and responses the paper addressed were different: they were attempts to alter the epistemic environment. And this relates to the tacit. Voluntarism does not hold for the tacit, which is to say, that which is produced by experience and by prior cognitive predispositions. The experiences of the digital world are subject to manipulation, and the manipulators can themselves be coerced. In this way, a person’s tacit sense of what is normal or acceptable can be manipulated. But the same sense can be the basis of rejection of claims made in the name of expert authority. One difference between overt coercion and tacit manipulation is that the manipulation of epistemically relevant experience, through such means as algorithms governing social media content, is hidden from the recipient, and more difficult to resist. But its effects are indirect, for example, in facilitating acceptance as normal. These effects are bound up with persuasion and acceptance generally, so this kind of manipulation represents an exercise of hidden power.

References

Cowling, M. Mill and Liberalism, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

Gigerenzer, G. “Psychological Challenges for Normative Models,” in: Gabbay, D.M. and Smets, Ph. (eds.), Handbook of Defeasible Reasoning and Uncertainty Management Systems, vol. 1. Netherlands: Kluwer, 1998, pp. 441–467.

Gigerenzer, G. Gut Feelings: The Intelligence of the Unconscious. New York: The Penguin Group, 2007.

Mill, J.S. “The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte,” The Westminster and Foreign Quarterly Review, April 1, 1865, pp. 309–405.

Mill, J.S. “Later Speculations of Auguste Comte,” The Westminster and Foreign Quarterly Review, July 1, 1865, pp. 2–42.

Mill, J.S. Inaugural Address Delivered to the University of St. Andrews, Feb. 1st 1867. London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer, 1867.

Mill, J.S. On the Logic of Moral Sciences. Chicago: Open Court, [1872] 1988.

Origgi, G. Reputation: What It Is and Why It Matters. Trans. by S. Holmes and N. Arikha. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2017.

Polanyi, M. Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. London: Routledge, 1958.

Popper, K. “Science: Conjectures and Refutations,” in: Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge, [1963] 1965. New York: Harper & Row, 1953, pp. 33–65.

Schmitt, C. The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and Failure of a Political Symbol. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, [1938] 2008.

Turner, S. “The Survey in Nineteenth-Century American Geology: The Evolution of a Form of Patronage,” Minerva, 1987, vol. 25 (3), pp. 282–330.

Turner, S. “Truth and Decision,” The Politics of Expertise. New York: Routledge, [1989] 2014, pp. 53–70.

Turner, S. Brains/Practices/Relativism: Social Theory after Cognitive Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002.

Turner, S. “The Social Study of Science before Kuhn,” in: Hackett, E.J., Amsterdamska, O., Lynch, M., and Wajcman, J. (eds.), The Handbook of Science and Technology Studies, 3rd ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2008, pp. 33–62.

Turner, S. “Normal Accidents of Expertise,” Minerva, 2010, vol. 48, pp. 239–258.

Turner, S. Understanding the Tacit. New York: Routledge, 2014.

Turner, S. “Tacit Knowledge Meets Analytic Kantianism,” Tradition & Discovery, 2014, vol. 41 (1), pp. 33–47.

Turner, S. The Politics of Expertise. New York: Routledge, 2014.

Turner, S. “Thinking about Think Tanks: Politics by Techno-Scientific Means,” in: Castro, J.E., Fowler, B., and Gomes, L. (eds.), Time, Science and the Critique of Technological Reason: Essays in Honour of Hermínio Martins. London: Palgrave, 2018, pp. 347–365.

Turner, S. “The Political Philosophy of Science in Historical Perspective: The Road through Popper and Polanyi to the Present,” in: Sassower, R. and Laor, N. (eds.), The Impact of Critical Rationalism: Expanding the Popperian Legacy through the Works of Ian C. Jarvie. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2018, pp. 257–271.

Turner, S. “Philosophical Argument and Wicked Problems,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 2018, vol. 48 (1), pp. 71–79.

Turner, S. “Habit Is Thus the Enormous Flywheel of Society: Pragmatism, Social Theory, and Cognitive Science,” in: Testa, I. and Caruana, F. (eds.), Habit: Pragmatist Approaches from Cognitive Neuroscience, Neuroscience, and Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2020, pp. 320–336.

Turner, S. “Curation: The Digital World of Manipulated Experience,” in: Nyíri, K. (ed.), Facing the Future, Facing the Screen (Perspectives on Visual Learning, vol. 5). Budapest: Hungarian Academy of Sciences, 2022, pp. 69–75.

Turner, S. “Expertise and Complex Organizations,” in: Eyal, G. and Medvetz, T. (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Expertise and Democratic Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2023, pp. 237–258.

Turner, S. “Polanyi and Tacit Knowledge,” in: Thompson, R. (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Implicit Cognition. London: Routledge, 2023, pp. 182–190.

Turner, S. “Making Collective Practices into Psychological Facts: The Russian Psychology Model,” in: Giovagnoli, R. & Lowe, R. (eds.), The Logic of Social Practices II, vol. 68, Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology. Springer, 2023, pp. 1–19.

Downloads

Published

2024-09-26

How to Cite

[1]
2024. TACIT COERCION: A REPLY. Epistemology & Philosophy of Science. 61, 3 (Sep. 2024), 93–104. DOI:https://doi.org/10.5840/eps202461344.